Renal transplant remains the treatment of choice for patients with end-stage renal disease. Human organs can be harvested from 2 main sources: living and deceased donors. Preference should be given to deceased-donor transplants since they represent the only source of organs for several nonrenal solid-organ transplants and the only modality where there is no risk to the donor. Unfortunately, even the most well-developed deceased-donor program (eg, the Spanish program) can barely cover 50% of its waiting list because the demand for deceased-donor organs far exceeds supply. The success of transplant surgery has created a waiting list dilemma. Despite all efforts, deceased-donor donation cannot meet current needs and therefore, living donation demands serious consideration. This is supported by the fact that the risk to live donors is minimal, graft survival is significantly better than that of deceased-donor kidneys regardless of HLA matching, and professional ethical philosophers have fewer difficulties with voluntary living donations than with the removal of an organ from a cadaver. This is especially true in our region. Living-related donation has always been acceptable ethically. It is, however, limited by the number of willing and qualified donors, the high incidence of familial renal diseases, and donor coercion (especially in our area). Living-unrelated donation increases the availability of donors, decreases the chances of coercion, and eliminates the problem of consanguinity. It raises, however, the ethical issues of commercialism, transplant tourism, and organ trafficking. The arguments for and against living-unrelated donation are innumerable. They have been the subject of several international forums and have raised endless discussions. We have set long ago a series of rules and regulations that are in close agreement with the recent Amsterdam and Kuwait resolutions. We have been continually modifying them over the last 15 years to try to implement our ideal, which is to protect the interest of the living donor and avoid commercialism.
Key words : Transplant, Donor organ, Ethics
Transplant is not a myth; it is no longer experimental. In 2007, transplant surgery is a recognized treatment modality. As of the end of 2004, there were 153 245 people living with a functioning transplant in the United States (1); many already have survived for more than 25 years. Although dialysis successfully prolongs the lives of many patients with end-stage renal disease, renal transplant remains their treatment of choice. Renal transplant offers longer patient survival, better quality of life, and it is a more economical option in the long term (2) (although the latter might not be universally true: in some countries, good quality dialysis might turn out to be less expensive than a good quality renal transplant) One cannot conceive of a good quality renal transplant that does not take advantage of state-of-the-art drugs for induction, maintenance, and short- and long-term prevention of complications. Recently developed drugs are not yet amenable to generic formulations and are excessively costly. Despite impressive scientific progress, cloning and xenotransplant are still experimental. They remain theoretical options (3, 4) that we cannot realistically depend on for the next 2 decades.
In the mean time, kidney transplant surgery must continue. Numerous studies have shown the advantages of early transplant, or even better, pre-emptive transplant (5). For the time being, only human kidneys can be used. Human organs can be harvested from 2 main sources: living donors and deceased donors. These 2 main sources can be subdivided further. Living donors can be genetically related or unrelated, and deceased donors can be brain-dead heart-beating donors or non–heart-beating donors (6, 7). The preference should go to deceased-donor donation since the outcome of deceased-donor kidneys is continually improving (with regard to surgical and preservation techniques and immunosuppression); deceased-donor donation is the only modality where there is, obviously, no risk to the donor; and deceased-donor donation is currently the only source of organs for many nonrenal solid-organ transplants such as a heart and a cornea. That is why the National Organization for Organ and Tissue Donation and Transplantation has spared no effort to promote deceased-donor donation in Lebanon. With limited legal and financial backing, the National Organization for Organ and Tissue Donation and Transplantation has been able to conduct several public information and education campaigns, deliver lectures in schools and universities, distribute posters to all intensive care units in the country, edit a pocket manual for organ and tissue donation (Lebanese model), inaugurate a Web site (www.nootdt.org), participate in the Beirut Marathon (2005), collaborate in organ donation and transplant congresses, organize 5 transplant procurement management courses, and conduct a statistical survey on the attitudes of different Lebanese communities toward organ and tissue donation.
Unfortunately, even the most well-developed deceased-donor program (eg, the Spanish program) can barely cover 50% of its waiting list (8). So the therapeutic promise of transplanting organs from deceased donors as envisioned by the pioneers of transplant has never been realized because the demand for deceased-donor organs has far exceeded the supply (9).
The very success of transplant surgery has led to our present problem: organ shortage. It has created a waiting list dilemma that must be solved. The number of people dying on waiting lists is progressively increasing. In 2000, almost 5000 people died on the waiting list in the United States. In July 2003, there was a total of 82 117 patients waiting for a solid organ transplant (10). This number reached 90 000 in 2005 (1).
To solve the problem of a continuously expanding waiting list 2 solutions are proposed: limiting access to the waiting list, and increasing the donor pool.
Limiting access to the transplant list
We have been, so far, very permissive in admitting patients to the waiting list (11). This is because, we, the transplanters, are reluctant to play God and decide who should and who should not receive a transplant. Should we adopt a purely utilitarian attitude? That is, should we ask, Who will benefit most? This debate is open to discussion. But are we not already playing God when we adhere to principles of organ allocation according to points (12) or when we select the recipient who should be attributed an extended criteria kidney (13)? With improved outcomes using organs from non–heart-beating donors (14), this source can now be promoted and will probably be better accepted socially, at least in societies where the concept of brain death is not universally agreed upon. However, we will be forced to acquire the know-how and the proper technical support and restrict it, initially, to younger donors and to well-experienced, structured, and well-established transplant programs, since a “young” program cannot afford failures!
Increasing the donor pool
Despite all our efforts, deceased-donor donation will not meet our needs. At this stage, we can either relax and delegate to others the responsibility of solving the problem while reserving the right to criticize, or try to find the most adequate solutions, make mistakes, be criticized but be modest enough to accept criticism, listen, learn, and attempt to correct our mistakes. After having relentlessly encouraged deceased-donor donation and exhausted our heart-beating and non–heart-beating deceased-donor possibilities, we must seriously consider living donation.
Is there justification for using living donors? Whether the live donor is related or unrelated, the medical risk, though minimal, is present. Our guiding principle should be primum nihil nocere (first, do no harm). Live kidney donation has been tolerated because:
Living-related donation has always been ethically accepted. It is, however, limited by the number of willing and qualified donors, the high incidence of familial renal diseases (especially in our area) (20), and the fact that coercion is always a latent problem in any living-related donation (17).
So, in practice, it is not that easy to find intrafamilial donors (it is barely 10% of the total). If we want to increase our pool of kidney donors, we must use living-unrelated donors. Using living-unrelated donors increases donor availability, decreases the chances of coercion, and eliminates the problem of consanguinity. Its use, however, raises the ethical issues of commercialism, transplant tourism, and organ trafficking. Among living-unrelated donors, the emotionally related ones have been classified separately and are ethically tolerated (16). We must bear in mind, however, that the ethical problem is not in the act of donation. It is in the motives behind the act.
The question now is: Do we have the right to judge these motives, and can we be accurate and fair in this judgment process? Every time we consider regulating living-unrelated donation, the objection from a Canadian potential recipient comes to our mind: “And who, pray tell me, gave you the right to make the rules by which my life has to be lived? I suppose this is just another example of the arrogance that you doctors show towards those who challenge your control of things” (21). The arguments for and against living-unrelated donors are innumerable. They have been the subject of several international forums and have raised endless discussions.
Under the pressure of organ shortage and scientific progress, even the World Health Organization (WHO) has had to modify its initial recommendations of 1991 (22). In May 2004, a WHO meeting in Geneva showed a clearly more tolerant attitude toward living donation (22). Along with the globalization of medicine, the initial Judeo-Christian moral concepts have been challenged regularly. Some principles, however, seem to have reached a general consensus. It is this general consensus that we should insist upon. This consensus has formed the basis of the Amsterdam resolutions in 2004 (23, 24) (Table 1), and we adopted it at the MESOT meeting held in Kuwait in 2006 (25) (Table 2). These resolutions underlie the proposals for living-unrelated donation in the Kingdom of Saudi Arabia. In Lebanon, for more than 15 years, we have been accepting living-unrelated donors. Although our conditions anti date the Amsterdam resolutions, they are almost the same. To implement our ideal—protect the interest of the living donor and avoid commercialism—we have set a series of rules and regulations that we continually modify.
To protect the donor:
To avoid commercialism:
What we hope to add to our present regulations include:
In conclusion, organ shortage remains a great challenge in solid organ transplant. We can solve it by refining our criteria for choosing recipients to have a more accurate estimate of the effective waiting list and by maximizing organ procurement by encouraging deceased-donor donation and utilizing non–heart-beating donation if allowed by culture and religion. The acceptance of living-unrelated donors at present seems inevitable. No effort should be spared, however, to prevent organ vending. We must protect the donor by allowing limited, regulated compensation and creating a donor registry. While some issues are clear with appropriate solutions, many others are complex with no definite answers. Social acceptance is the final arbiter of ethics.
References:
Volume : 5
Issue : 2
Pages : 633 - 637
From the 1Lebanese Institute for Renal Diseases and the 2National Organization for Organ and Tissue Donation and Transplantation, Beirut, Lebanon
Address reprint requests to: Antoine Stephan, MD, Lebanese Institute for Renal Diseases, PO Box: 32-11, Beirut, Lebanon
Phone: +961 1 33 89 31
Fax: +961 1 33 20 44
E-mail: lird@cyberia.net.lb
Table 1. Amsterdam resolutions, April 2004 (23)
Table 2. Kuwait statement, November 2006